63 pages • 2 hours read
Karl PopperA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Falsifiability represents the core of Popper’s thesis in The Logic of Scientific Discovery. His work reacts to the tradition of epistemological argument surrounding verification and rationalism. For centuries, philosophers explored the roles of experience and logic in the acquisition and development of knowledge. Rationalists proposed that knowledge is born through reason while empiricists center their theory of knowledge on experience. Popper builds his philosophy of falsifiability upon the foundation set by Immanuel Kant, who reconciled the two camps. Popper redefines empiric science as that which marries experience and logic. However, he emphasizes that both these elements must have a singular aim: falsifiability.
Popper’s methodology for testing utilizes experience through observable data. He rejects scientific methodology that suggests there are hidden or forbidden elements that cannot be observed in experimentation. Instead, hypotheses must be selected for their observable occurrences. Reason, or logic, should be deductive, and it is a necessary element of the scientific method. Rather than emphasizing what humans can know with certainty, falsifiability aims to eliminate possibilities. Simplicity plays an important role in this overarching goal. An idea that is simple leads to clarified testing and outcomes. Popper argues that the simpler a theory is the easier it is to falsify. For Popper, science should pass theories and ideas through a sieve. What is left in the sieve represents that which has been eliminated through falsifiability. Although the theories will never be perfectly and totally refined, scientists can gain a better understanding of the world and build theories off what has been left behind.
For Popper, the work of science is never complete. The field of application holds an infinite number of points of inquiry. He illustrates this idea by mapping the field of application on a circle. The radius through the circle represents a statement, and the points along the radius represent the various intersections of ideas. Popper maintains that there will always be basic statements within a theoretical set that are forbidden; no amount of scientific experimentation or inquiry will lead to a universal truth or the verification of an idea. Therefore, all scientific inquiry should seek to falsify claims rather than affirm them. Popper argues that by aiming for falsifiability, theories are further refined rather than verified. If experimentation leads to corroboration, this does not prove the statement. Instead, it contributes to refinement and opens the opportunity for further testing. Any scientific approach that does not emphasize falsifiability is representative of non-science and conventionalist practices.
Popper presents verification and falsification as asymmetrical. They are inequal in weight. For the philosopher, verification places limits on science. He correlates verification with belief and conventionalism. The latter builds an understanding of the world based on faith and unspoken rules. Conventionalism uses an ad hoc logical fallacy to support the suppression of falsifying and contradictory evidence. It suggests that there are certain points of data that can never be observed but should be accepted.
Carl Sagan illustrates the problem with this way of approaching science in his book The Demon-Haunted World (1995). Sagan describes inviting his neighbor to come over to see the dragon in his garage. When the neighbor peers into the room, she sees nothing. Sagan replies that he forgot to mention that the dragon is invisible. As the neighbor seeks other points of data, such as the dragon’s footprints in the dirt on the floor, Sagan creates new theories that explain away the lack of observable data. To answer the problem with footprints, Sagan replies that the dragon floats in the air. Sagan’s use of the dragon to illustrate this idea is intentional. Most would agree that dragons do not exist, thereby rendering the example ludicrous. However, Sagan argues that there is no difference between establishing belief in an invisible dragon utilizing non-observable data and the same methods that are used in scientific inquiry in real life.
By accepting conventionalist logic, humans agree to a low standard of scientific inquiry. Ideas are merely accepted and never challenged. Popper imagines a future of scientific inquiry that is never-ending. Ideas build on one another, but the tower is allowed to topple when theories are falsified. Inductive reasoning makes broad general statements based on experience. Popper simplifies his ideas about inductive reasoning early in the book with the swan example. In this illustration, a scientist observes a large number of swans, all of which are white. The scientist then casts a sweeping net of generalization: “All swans are white.” This represents inductive reasoning. At first glance, this form of logic makes sense. If a person has cut into one hundred apples and each apple had seeds inside, it is sensical to assume that all apples have seeds inside. Popper would suggest, however, that it only takes the existence of one apple without seeds or one swan that is not white to falsify that claim.
Popper’s emphasis on establishing a boundary between science and non-science is better understood within the historical context during which he wrote The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Worried about the altering landscape of Europe prior to World War II and his own Jewish identity, Popper hoped to write something that would help him gain a position outside of Austria. However, the connection has further implications. The period was riddled with pseudoscientific arguments, including those within the racist field of eugenics. Popular scientists made sweeping generalizations and established laws of “truth” based on limited corroboration and conventionalist practices to support racist ideologies. The rise of Naziism had a foundation of 19th-century racist pseudoscience. For example, French scientist Paul Broca changed how humans understood the brain; in the 1860s, Broca discovered the part of the brain that controls speech. However, he also believed that the brains of different races of people were vastly different. He used his inductive reasoning to suggest that people of color were less intelligent than those of white, European descent. In the early 20th century, immigrants to the United States were required to take IQ tests created by American scientists; this test relied heavily upon cultural background to be successful. This process of eliminating people of color from crossing American shores paraded as science, but it was inductive logic predicated upon a racist belief that one group of people was better than all others. Popper understood the importance of drawing a line between science and pseudoscience. Inductivist practices not only limited science; they were dangerous.
In the work, Popper argues that areas like metaphysics and psychoanalysis utilize inductive reasoning and are, therefore, non-scientific. The line that marks the distinction is skepticism. Popper advocates for deductive reasoning that utilizes falsifiability. Rather than seeking to verify or justify ideas, deductive reasoning seeks to prove them wrong. This has important connotations for the historical context described above. Rather than establishing a theory based upon personal belief and values and then supporting the idea through various forms of insufficient evidence, deductive reasoning takes a theory and applies rigorous testing to show that it does not work. In doing so, the scientist gains a better understanding of how the world does not work, which then provides a better understanding of how it does work. This is why Popper argues that all good scientific methodology should be prohibitive. It should place limitations on what it seeks to test, but it should not limit science. This means that deductive logic is open to being falsified; it is open to new ideas. Pseudoscience, on the other hand, establishes a belief and ignores any evidence that may challenge it. The line between science and non-science is best summarized in Popper’s final words in Chapter 10: “Science never pursues the illusory aim of making its answers final, or even probable” (281).
By Karl Popper