logo

43 pages 1 hour read

Edmund Burke

Reflections On The Revolution In France

Nonfiction | Essay / Speech | Adult | Published in 1790

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Key Figures

Edmund Burke

Edmund Burke (1729-1797) writes Reflections on the Revolution in France in 1790. For much of the latter eighteenth century, Burke serves as a major figure in British politics in the Whig party, the liberal faction of British parliament. He sides with reform and justice in the prominent cases of the day, and he faces many: the American Revolution, issues of unification in Ireland, and justice for imperial India and its governance.

However, late in his political career, his party faces a divide, with more liberal members of the party favoring radical ideas, particularly those championed by the Enlightenment. During this time, people question institutions that previously enjoyed unfettered power: monarchies, the church, the nobility. Burke finds himself on the conservative side of his party, arguing for the time-proven value of these institutions against the more radical members of his party, who are enamored with the idea of a government founded on an abstraction Burke has difficultly defining: the Rights of Man. At this point, Burke pens Reflections on the Revolution in France, revealing his allegiance to and respect for the British constitution and British politics. 

Nationalism over any radical idea or abstraction defines Burke’s character. He identifies as proudly British, drawing ties to Britain and breaking ties with the Enlightenment, writing, “[a] spirit of innovation is generally a result of a selfish temper and confined views. People will not look forward to posterity who never look backward to their ancestors” (33). He calls himself a preserver of culture, society, law and order. Furthermore, he draws an analogy between himself and Britain by speaking in the first-person plural: he binds his faith, with the rest of his countrymen, to the historical wisdom of Britain’s political and social makeup, hailing the monarch, landed nobility, and the standing institutions of England that radical thinkers decry:

[…] it is vain to talk to them of the practice of their ancestors, the fundamental laws of their country, the fixed form of a constitution, whose merits are confirmed by the solid test of long experience, and an increasing public strength and national prosperity” (58).

Revealed in Reflections on the Revolution in France, Burke favors a conservative approach over radical change; humor and hyperbole intermix with the seriousness of his plea to his countrymen, who, enamored with the French Revolution, call for similar change. Burke writes, “I know that we are supposed a dull sluggish race, rendered passive by finding our situation tolerable; and prevented by a mediocrity of freedom from ever attaining to its full perfection” (55). Here, he illustrates the comedy of excess his opponents clamor for, just as he pokes fun at his own pride in an imperfect-but-working system. This is perhaps the greatest illustration of Burke’s character as he sees it; he is, ultimately, a political creature, one endowed with having to weigh the great consequences of law and order. He understands the danger of abstractions in practice and uses the analogy of the French Revolution to warn his countrymen that their “tolerable” (55) circumstances were, in fact, a long-living testimony to greatness. He urges the British to “[stand] on the firm ground of the British constitution, […] rather than attempt to follow in their desperate flights” of the French (249).

Charles-Jean-François Depont

Charles-Jean-François Depont is a French aristocrat and family friend of Burke. Upon meeting Burke, he requests Burke’s observations on the events of the National Assembly thus far. Burke maintains the style of the letter, forming Reflections on the Revolution in France in the epistolary tradition, using informal and shifting styles, but it is clear that Depont is not the main audience for this letter. Depont serves to ignite a much larger political cause closer to Burke’s heart: discouraging a revolution in England, so Depont’s personal character subverts to more of an instrument for Burke’s true purpose. 

Richard Price

Dr. Richard Price (1723-1791) is a preacher in the Unitarian sect, to whom Burke refers to frequently in Reflections on the Revolution in France. Price enjoys membership in one of the radical Whig societies, the Revolutionary Society, which disseminates ideas in favor of the French Revolution. Burke paraphrases one of Price’s sermons:

I cannot conclude without recalling particularly to your recollection a consideration which I have more than once alluded to, and which probably your thoughts have been all along anticipating, a consideration with which my mind is impressed more than I can express. I mean the consideration of the favorableness of the present times to all exertions to the cause of liberty(53).

These words serve as the catalyst for Burke’s letter: the real audience for Burke’s tract on conservatism remains those he fears will take Price’s words to heart.

Price follows the more liberal line of Whig-Party thinking; he affiliates himself with many revolutionary thinkers of the day and often intermingles politics in his sermons. Subjectively, Burke refers to Price’s sermons as “[…] mixed up in a sort of porridge of various political opinions and reflections: but the revolution in France is the grand ingredient in the cauldron” (10-11).

He is, as Burke has feared, something of an abstract idea himself: “a political preacher” (53), a powerful speaker, infusing the audience with grand ideas, but, to Burke’s thinking, with little thought to the ramifications of putting those abstract ideas into practice. Also, in radical contrast to Burke’s more fixed notions on what clergy should provide during sermon, Burke writes, “Supposing, however, that something like moderation were visible in this political sermon, yet politics and the pulpit are terms that have little agreement. No sound ought to be heard in the church but the healing voice of Christian charity” (11-12). This aligns with both men’s character; the more-radical Price feels comfortable assuming the role of both religious and political healer, whereas Burke believes politics a specialized field and religion the institution of Providence.  

Price’s character embodies the political radicalism Burke claims unnecessary. Price advocates swift change that threatens order (Burke even goes as far as to draw a parallel between Price and Reverend Hugh Peters, a prominent player in the beheading of Charles I). Further, it is Price’s sermon, more so than the request of Depont (Burke’s French friend), that is the galvanizing force driving Burke to write this letter. Burke fears sermons like his will foster similar revolutionary action in Britain. In an effort to discredit Price’s ideas further, Burke theorizes, “Those who quit their proper character, to assume that what does not belong to them, are, for the great part, are ignorant both of the character they leave, and of the character they assume” (12). Again, this underscores Burke’s belief that men philosophize on matters of great import (they may even spur men into action), but they lack little practical experience in the matters of which they speak. By Burke’s admission, Price is an influential and popular orator; the latter, as with Burke’s entire audience in Reflections on the Revolution in France, should exercise more conservatism with such an important subject.

To Burke, Price’s ideology is particular dangerous, and Burke places Price and his followers in line with people who preach change for the sake of change. Burke states:

His zeal is of a curious character. It is not for the propagation of his own opinions, but of any opinions. It is not for the diffusion of truth, but for the spreading of contradiction. Let the noble teachers but dissent, it is no matter from whom or from what (12).

Burke uses the first part of his letter to clarify points of confusion he finds in Price’s sermon, particularly those in which Price argues the British have the right to cashier their king and elect their own government.

King Louis XVI

At the time the National Assembly met, the reigning monarch of France was Louis XVI (1754-1793), who sat on the throne as an absolute monarch; this distinguishes his position from that of the then-current British monarch, George III, a constitutional monarch (the former having absolute power over the country, appointing all orders of government, the latter answerable to governing bodies). Deposed as an absolute monarch and ultimately relegated by the Assembly as a limited-power executive hand of the French government, Louis XVI inherits the throne through the normal route: right of succession. 

Burke describes Louis XVI’s character in a fairly objective manner; he points out that the role of an absolute monarch makes as much sense as its other extreme, a direct democracy, as Burke believes both forms of government are ripe for tyranny (125). Price illustrates Louis XVI as an “arbitrary monarch” (82), a claim to which the French Revolution must agree, in order to depose him. According to Burke, no concrete evidence exists to suggest Louis the XVI, aside from some error in leniency and judgment to which all kings are capable, subjects his citizens to any type of tyranny justifying a revolution over a reformation.

In dramatic accounts of his situation, Burke offers a humanized account of Louis XVI:

As a man, it became him to feel for his wife and his children, and the faithful guards of his person, that were massacred in cold blood about him; as a prince, it became him to feel for the strange and frightful transformation of his civilized subjects, and to be more grieved for them, than solicitous for himself (75).

Here, Burke supposes that the king suffers the great loss of dignity in his post and also in that of the character of his people: he is the representation of their chivalry and civility, and in their crass treatment of him and his family, that spirit dies.

Queen Marie Antoinette

Marie Antoinette (1755-1793) ruled as the queen of France at the time of Burke’s writing. An even more polarizing figure with the public, Burke offers a less objective account of the Queen in Reflections on the Revolution in France. Though much of the nobility and chivalry that applies to her husband’s character carries over to Burke’s depiction of Marie Antoinette, the analogy is even more dramatic due to what Burke describes as her abundantly charming and graceful nature. To that end, he expresses shock that no person would rush to her aid, using her abandonment as proof “[the] age of chivalry is gone. That of sophisters, economists, and calculators, has succeeded; and the glory of Europe is extinguished for ever” (76). To that end, Marie Antoinette’s dignified regality, manners, and honor inspire the chivalry that gives Europe its character. If her character is assassinated in such a fashion, Burke reasons, then European character on the whole suffers.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text