58 pages • 1 hour read
Thomas HobbesA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Given the natural laws put forth in previous chapters, Hobbes argues that the most advantageous state of being for humankind is to live in a commonwealth, a sovereign state led by either a single individual or an assembly of individuals. In justifying why this is, the author poses a question: Why can’t humankind live peaceably like other sociable animals such as bees and ants? To that, Hobbes writes that humans, unlike animals, are in a state of constant competition for honor and dignity. Moreover, humans are capable of deceiving one another through language. Perhaps most importantly, humans can distinguish between what is best for themselves and what is best for the community. Thus, while animals agree on a common good through natural means, humankind relies on covenants with one another.
In Hobbes’s view the most effective covenant under which humankind may live is the commonwealth, a sovereign state united under one ruler or one ruling assembly. He likens this leader—heretofore referred to as a sovereign—as the leviathan, the monstrous sea serpent from the Book of Job in the Bible. He writes, “This is the generation of that great LEVIATHAN, or rather, to speak more reverently, of that mortal god to which we owe, under the immortal God, our peace and defence” (109).
Finally, Hobbes divides commonwealths into two types: commonwealths of institution and commonwealths of acquisition. A commonwealth of institution is created when a group of people agrees to elevate an individual or assembly to the status of sovereign. A commonwealth of acquisition is created when a sovereign seizes power through military force.
Hobbes writes that regardless of whether an individual votes for or against a sovereign, that individual authorizes every action of their sovereign by virtue of choosing to live peaceably in a community, as natural law dictates. Therefore, Hobbes believes every action taken by a sovereign is just because it is done by the authority of the men and women who consent to be ruled. In turn, every act of disobedience undertaken by a subject against the sovereign is unjust. In short, Hobbes writes, “Because every subject is by this institution author of all the actions and judgements of the sovereign instituted, it follows that whatsoever he doth, can be no injury to any of his subjects” (112).
The rights of a sovereign are therefore extensive and varied, Hobbes writes. They include evaluating which opinions and doctrines are averse to the public good, creating and adjudicating laws, doling out reward and punishment alike, and selecting ministers and counselors. Foremost among these rights, however, is the right to make war and peace with fellow nations in the interest of protecting the safety of subjects. While many of these rights can be transferred to other individuals, Hobbes cautions against this because it may lead to division and eventually civil war.
Among commonwealths, Hobbes identifies three types: monarchy, democracy, and aristocracy. In a monarchy absolute power is held by one individual, normally referred to as a king or a queen. In a democracy power is held by an assembly of individuals who are broadly representative of the general public. Finally, in an aristocracy power is held by an assembly of individuals who represent merely a small elite part of the general public.
In comparing the virtues of these three types, Hobbes prefers monarchies for a number of reasons. For one, he writes, “A monarch cannot disagree with himself, out of envy or interest; but an assembly may; and that to such a height as may produce civil war” (121). While all sovereigns are threatened by the manipulations of favorites or flatterers, Hobbes argues that this risk is mitigated in monarchies because one individual will have fewer favorites than an assembly of individuals.
Hobbes turns to matters related to commonwealths by acquisition. The nature and extent of the sovereign’s power is the same, he argues, in both commonwealths by institution and commonwealths by acquisition. The latter, he adds, “differeth from sovereignty by institution only in this, that men who choose their sovereign do it for fear of one another, and not of him whom they institute: but in this case, they subject themselves to him they are afraid of” (127).
Hobbes also writes briefly of paternal dominion under which obedience is required toward a dominant parent, depending on either contract or custom. This may be a father or a mother, but in all cases it consists of one ultimate individual, as a person cannot serve two masters.
Despotical dominion, meanwhile, exists when a ruler obtains sovereignty through conquest. When a subject of a conquered nation is vanquished—that is to say, when they surrender to the will of the conqueror—that individual tacitly consents to become a servant of the new sovereign. Hobbes draws a distinction between a servant and a slave, the latter of whom never had the opportunity to submit and is therefore justified in escaping or killing their master.
Finally, Hobbes draws on biblical scripture to justify a subject’s obedience to a master. He cites the absolute obedience God commands that subjects pay to Moses, their sovereign leader at that time. He also cites Jesus’s exhortation that subjects pay taxes to Caesar even though they do not worship the same deity.
Hobbes defines liberty as “the absence of opposition (by opposition, I mean external impediments of motion); and may be applied no less to irrational and inanimate creatures than to rational” (136). Given that humans’ liberty is manifested in what they will themselves to do or not do, the concept of liberty is perfectly consistent with both fear and necessity. For example, one may willingly avoid danger or willingly feed him or herself in order to survive. By that same token, an action taken or not taken in a commonwealth out of fear of civil consequences is also consistent with liberty because individuals willingly consent to be ruled. For that reason, liberty does not include an exemption from the laws of a commonwealth.
Hobbes details the workings of various political and private systems in a commonwealth. A political system, he writes, is one imbued with official authority by the sovereign, like an office of taxation. A private system, meanwhile, is organized by subjects and operates only with whatever authority it is tacitly allowed by the absence of any law prohibiting it. These may include guilds among merchants or even informal gatherings of individuals for the purpose of leisure or commerce.
In a commonwealth, Hobbes writes, sovereign monarchs or assemblies will appoint various ministers to act on the sovereign’s behalf. They are generally committed to administering duties related to a part of a kingdom, like the treasury or a militia, but theoretically may be charged with administering the entirety of a kingdom if the sovereign so chooses. Hobbes distinguishes ministers from other government workers like valets or infantrymen because those individuals are not given the power to command others.
By nutrition, Hobbes means the commodities and other valued resources used for the benefit of a commonwealth and its subjects. These include land, which according to Hobbes should be assigned to subjects by the sovereign. They also include gold and silver, which are primarily used to build and maintain armies for the purpose of protecting subjects or expanding a commonwealth’s dominion.
By procreation, Hobbes means the colonies of a commonwealth, which he likens to its children. As long as they remain under the dominion of the sovereign, they are known as provinces. If at any point the sovereign releases these colonies from his or her dominion, they become new commonwealths themselves.
In advising sovereigns how to best receive counsel, Hobbes first distinguishes between command, counsel, and exhortation. The definition of command is self-evident and can only justly arise from the sovereign or an individual who is given the authorization to command from the sovereign. The chief difference between command and counsel, Hobbes writes, is that a command is designed to benefit the individual who issues it, while a piece of counsel is designed to benefit the individual who receives it. Meanwhile, exhortation is counsel given with a vehement desire for this advice to be followed and is often issued by corrupt individuals with agendas that run counter to the sovereign and the public good.
An extension of his state of nature theory, Hobbes’s theory of social contracts—or covenants, as he calls them—has had an enormous impact on Western thought. To Hobbes, the making and keeping of covenants is as much a part of natural law as the right for self-preservation. Once again, it is instructive to compare Hobbes’s theories to the philosophers who followed in his wake. For example, Hobbes seems to anticipate Rousseau’s argument a century in advance that humans are naturally social creatures and therefore are unlikely to fall into the state of barbarism Hobbes imagines in nature. In comparing humankind to insects, Hobbes writes, “These creatures, having not, as man, the use of reason, do not see, nor think they see, any fault in the administration of their common business: men, however, think themselves wiser than others, causing civil war” (108).
To that, Rousseau might argue that by the time humans began to thrive in great enough numbers to compete with one another over resources, they would have already amassed into family units and clans, preventing the condition of all-out war Hobbes imagines. This isn’t to say that Locke and Rousseau do not believe humankind does not benefit from covenants or contracts with sovereign authorities. All three believe that sovereigns receive their authority from the implicit or explicit consent of the governed and not from God, as the then-prevalent divine right of kings doctrine stipulated. Rather, the biggest place of disagreement between Hobbes and his successors pertains to how these covenants are made and the conditions under which they may be broken.
In Leviathan there is some lack of clarity as to precisely when each subject is said to consent to a sovereign’s rule. Hobbes’s argument that subjects of any kingdom have already provided tacit consent to be governed relies solely on his vision of the state of nature as being barbaric and unproductive toward each individual’s self-preservation, a precept to which Locke and Rousseau object. After all, monarchs are rarely elected by popular vote. And while it is reasonable to expect, say, a citizen of the United States to obey the president even if that person cast a vote for somebody else, in that case the individual gives consent by participating in the democratic process and pledging to accept its results.
This issue of consent is complicated even further in the cases of sovereignty by acquisition, in which a vanquished sovereign loses power over his or her dominion and subjects by surrendering them to a foreign invader. Hobbes would argue that by consenting to the rule of their previous sovereign, they must own all of that individual’s actions, including the act of surrender and consequent transfer of power to the new sovereign. This, however, would seem to contradict Hobbes’s precept that a covenant between sovereign and subject is broken when that sovereign can no longer protect the people from invasion. Under Hobbes’s own logic, then, how is the transfer of consent from the vanquished sovereign to the victorious one supposed to be assumed; especially if those subjects refuse to live peaceably under the new sovereign because they do not share the same values or religion? On that note, is the state of civil war Hobbes so fears that much worse than the reality of separate sovereign dominions in a state of near-constant war with one another, which were the conditions Europe found itself in for much of the past thousand years?
From these contradictions and concerns, one might reasonably look to the social contract theorists who followed in Hobbes’s wake, like Locke and Rousseau. For Locke, the social contract rests not on an effort to prevent a natural state of total war but on the notion of private property. The moment humans decide to leave the state of nature by laying claim to possessions, parcels of land, and even their own bodies, a civil government is needed to protect these rights. According to Locke, when families and clans organize into civil societies, they submit themselves not to a single monarch to whom they owe eternal obedience but to the will of the majority, which is mutable. Thus, there are numerous conditions under which citizens may justly rebel against sovereign power, at least under Locke’s view of government. Indeed, Locke’s work was extraordinarily influential on Thomas Jefferson and other participants in the American Revolution. Moreover, Locke’s less grim view of the state of nature allows him to envision conditions under which the populace rejects civil government outright, opting instead to return to natural living.
Like Locke, much of Rousseau’s social contract theory rests on the introduction of private property, which he terms a fall from grace out of a simpler, more idyllic state of nature. Without a civil government to pass laws tending toward better equity, humankind persists in a state of extreme inequality, as those who do not own much property or any at all are necessarily subservient to those who do. This is the fundamental problem Rousseau seeks to address with his 1762 work The Social Contract. Contrary to Hobbes, Rousseau believes that the fundamental contract on which a civil society is built is not the covenant between subject and sovereign but the covenant among all individuals to live peaceably. Which isn’t to say there is no covenant between democratically elected rulers and citizens, only that the terms of this covenant demand that the ruler work toward the good of the people or else the people may justly rebel. This is a clear contradiction of Hobbes’s theory that the sovereign, once elevated at the people’s consent, is essentially incapable of any action that would justify rebellion.
It’s worth pointing out that Rousseau’s idea of democracy differs from Hobbes’s in that Hobbes is content to place sovereignty in the hands of a group that is representative of the whole but not the whole itself. Rousseau, on the other hand, argues that each individual citizen has a right to participate in the decision-making process. As such, a Rousseauian democracy may only be viable in relatively small geographic areas where the citizens, within reason, know and understand one another. It would therefore be of great interest to know if Rousseau would rightly consider the modern United States properly democratic under his terms. Moreover, Rousseau’s guidance that the most effective democracies are organized by small groups of people is complicated by the difficulties these communities would necessarily face in protecting themselves from foreign invaders, which is arguably the most crucial duty of a sovereign, at least in Hobbes’s telling. So it is that all three of these theories are exactly that: theoretical. And given that each of them has flaws and virtues, it’s instructive to examine Hobbes’s theories of states of nature and social contracts as part of a dialogue with those who followed in his wake.
The differences between Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau are perhaps best illustrated by the book’s dominant symbol: the leviathan. Aside from the title, it is in these chapters that Hobbes first mentions the monster by name. In the Book of Job, God frames the sea creature as a menace so fearsome that no individual who encounters it can expect to survive. While this may seem like an odd symbol for Hobbes to use to describe a sovereign to whom we give consent to rule, it highlights the extent to which rulers must rely on fear to induce obedience. This runs counter to Lockeian and Rousseauian formulations of the social contract, in which the ruler has as much if not more to fear from the people, as opposed to the other way around.