logo

58 pages 1 hour read

Amartya Sen

Development As Freedom

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1999

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Chapters 11-12Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Chapter 11 Summary

Sen believes people can change the world through rational choices. This requires a framework to evaluate options, institutions to further goals and values, and behavioral norms that fit these ends. Yet, many skeptics challenge the possibility of rationally shaping the world in this way. Some question the possibility of society agreeing on a common evaluative framework. Kenneth Arrow has mathematically demonstrated this in his “impossibility theorem” that a ranked-choice voting system—in which people decide between more than two options by ranking preferences—always has the possibility of leading to inconsistent outcomes with decreased happiness. To simplify, the preference of the majority may come at the expense of the minority, like two people deciding to split a cake between themselves while giving nothing to the third. However, Arrow’s theorem doesn’t account for decision-making that incorporates a different informational base beyond simple ranked preferences—that is, concerns about poverty and equality. More generally, diverse opinions can be overcome by gradually building social consensus. Many rational decisions can be implemented even with imperfect consensus.

Other skeptics point to the pervasive influence of unintended consequences. Sen says that people have learned from failures and accomplished many things they did intend, such as improving literacy. China’s economic and social planning has spawned some negative unintended and unforeseen consequences, such as a rise in the deaths of female children; but the fact that they did not foresee these consequences does not mean they could not have anticipated them. Such unintended consequences can be remedied as they arise. On a more theoretical plane, Adam Smith, who was an ardent critic of the rich, famously noted that people’s selfish economic decisions had effects they did not directly intend on others, but the sum of these effects could lead to greater efficiency and prosperity. Carl Menger and Friedrich Hayek have made this principle central to economics, and some critics argue that this shows rational planning is impossible. The basis of economic analysis, however, is that these unintended consequences are rationally predictable, and therefore, people can shape their choices in light of that knowledge.

The Smithian market assumes that people act out of self-interest, and a final group of skeptics insist that idealistic appeals to values or the common good—even if based in reason—ultimately will not alter people’s naturally selfish behavior. Sen disagrees, arguing that a wide range of scholarship has demonstrated that ideas of justice are already rooted in society and do influence behavior. Even capitalism works in part because people accept norms about negotiations and contracts that do not need to be litigated in every deal; it relies on a degree of trust and transparency. Regions that are newly adopting capitalism—such as Eastern Europe—have struggled to build up those behavioral norms in business. Capitalist values are not sufficient in themselves to deal with some public goods, such as clean air and water; but they may be compatible with it, especially when taking Adam Smith’s call for regulation to rein in “prodigals,” or the rich who waste wealth rather than investing it in socially or economically useful ways.

“Rational choice” should not be reduced to self-interest. A person may rationally choose to help others out of sympathy or out of commitment to principles such as justice. Adam Smith himself acknowledged the importance of these higher motivations that may lead someone to choose an action that requires sacrifice: That is, to act against their apparent self-interest. People may follow values due to several factors: their own reasoning, social convention, or the influence of public discussion. Evidence also suggests behavioral systems that value justice lead to greater economic prosperity, and therefore, may be more likely to survive and spread in a kind of evolutionary selection. Corruption, for example, can be fought by trying to remove the economic incentive to accept bribes or increasing punishments for doing so. However, the most effective way of eliminating corruption and its negative effects on economic growth is changing behavioral norms. Countries with low rates of corruption have established norms of behavior in their culture, and as a result, many officials do not even consider selling their power. Creating such established norms is no easy task, but the appearance of these norms in countries where they did not previously exist proves that they can grow over time. Refusing bribes, in these cases, comes out of cultural values rather than self-interest, and it rationally leads to a better society and economy. Self-interest does not explain all behavior.

Chapter 12 Summary

As a reflective species, humans ought to recognize our interdependence and responsibility for our world and each other. This is not to slight personal responsibility. Some critics complain that the rhetoric of interdependence leads to a “nanny state” that debilitates people’s control over their lives. Too many people, however, lack the economic, social, or political power to change their circumstances. An authentic sense of interdependence means accepting the social responsibility to support others’ freedom. That, in turn, enables marginalized people to become true agents who are able to exercise personal responsibility over their lives.

The freedom-oriented approach outlined in this book allows a flexible approach to envisioning and working to create a better society. Its goal is simply to enhance “our capability to lead the kind of lives we have reason to value” (285). In other words, this approach begins with the diversity of goals that people have, emphasizes their personal freedom and responsibility, allows for a healthy debate on how to balance freedoms with concerns about inequality, and rejects authorities’ claims to know what is best. It has a measurable component in judging whether people are actually capable of living a life with sufficient food, medical care, civil liberty, and other such goods. It is a more holistic approach that mere GNP. This approach rejects any specific formula in favor of identifying key concerns that people in a society—as free agents—can use to rationally discuss and choose their preferred balance. Such free discussion—if it truly includes the voices of marginalized people and places a premium on freedom—should gradually form a public conscience that rejects manifest injustice. This process of free discussion has an intrinsic value in this freedom-based approach that traditional development-centered thought often ignores. The idea of development as freedom also highlights the opportunities that people have rather than focusing on one vision of what is possible, which can be limited by a simple analysis of end results. Consideration of both “process” and “opportunity” sets this approach apart from other contemporary economic systems.

While prioritizing freedom over GNP cuts against the grain of modern economic thought, such concern for the way wealth supports human freedom has a long history. Many foundational economic thinkers have pondered this broader context for wealth, including such diverse figures as Aristotle, Adam Smith, Karl Marx, Jeremy Bentham, and Friedrich Hayek. Modern economic thought has at least increasingly recognized the importance of human capital in development alongside traditional capital (money, land, machines, etc.). Too often, it still sees people’s capabilities as a mere means to improved production rather than abilities that have value because they empower people to choose the lives they desire. Capabilities do not just have an indirect role in influencing the economy; they also indirectly influence social status and (as desirable freedoms) directly constitute part of a person’s wellbeing. Educating a person, for example, may make them a better worker (that is, improved human capital), but it also opens up new vistas in their life, along with opportunities to engage in literate society and political debate. A traditional economic analysis would miss these broader capabilities. Moreover, focusing merely on increased production misses the point of why economic development matters in the first place: It exists to fulfill people’s desire for a better life.

Chapters 11-12 Analysis

In these final chapters, Sen turns to a more theoretical and idealistic plane. He begins by summarizing his pioneering work on social choice theory, though he leaves out the complex mathematics and theorization in order to tune his material to the general lay reader. Social choice theory uses primarily mathematical models to analyze how groups of people can select between preferences, especially in voting systems, and the effects of those processes and results on utility. Kenneth Arrow, whom Sen knew and refers to frequently here, established the field. Sen has played a key role in expanding it, including analyzing how it can function as a framework for evaluating results in society as a whole and showing that capabilities can replace utility as an effective measure. Given the popular nature of this book, Sen highlights his conclusions in this field while merely skimming through the technical arguments that brought him to these conclusions. Sen also mentions John Rawls, and Sen echoes that philosopher’s political liberalism when professing his own belief in the ability of public debate to build consensus on values. Sen also agrees with Rawls’s assertion that even imperfect consensus can normally suffice to guide rational policy.

These final chapters also bring together Sen’s three major themes under the rubric of rational choice through public, democratic discussion. The ability to have such a discussion presumes civil rights, such as freedom of speech and freedom of the press. It also indirectly relies on freedoms (in Sen’s broad sense of the term), such as education and social acceptance, that would allow people to participate in a rational, productive manner. Sen argues that by having the opportunity to do, people can identify the freedoms they need in their lives for their own wellbeing; they can then work together to build strategies that allow everyone to obtain what they need. In this way, Sen’s idea of rational public debates have Freedom as the Means and End of Development.

These debates, however, will only work if the voices of those suffering unfreedoms can make themselves heard—this leads into Sen’s argument about The Importance of Empowering Marginalized People. Only then can problems be correctly identified. Then, previously disenfranchised people can help shape policies that avoid unfortunate side effects while giving these people the kind of life they actually want. This might not necessarily be the same thing as the elites claim they want. Removing barriers to marginalized people actively participating in the solutions unleashes a powerful amount of human capital to build people’s capacities and functionings.

Sen also continues championing The Need for Holistic Measurements of Development since this will give a truer picture of the needs of those suffering unfreedoms. Mere GNP per capita will not satisfy their desires for wellbeing, especially if there is great inequality in the distribution of wealth. Sen stresses that he has “not argued for some specific formula to ‘settle’ this question” of how to balance different concerns about rights versus consequences or aggregate versus individual good (286). He believes that each society should come to its own balance, and that balance may differ from one place to another. However, he is arguing that society needs to consider the full range of freedoms that impact people’s wellbeing and use that information to have discussions about how to create a just society. He believes that society will reject severe instances of injustice if they have this kind of free and informed discussion, including the voices of marginalized people. He acknowledges that in cases of entrenched prejudice, this may be “a challenging and laborious process” (287). However, if freedom of speech is guaranteed and extended to minorities, then people can achieve this process of recognizing and renouncing injustice. He has faith in the human capacity to do so.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text